Skip to main content
Log in

Addiction and self-determination: A phenomenological approach

  • Published:
Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this article, I focus on possibly impaired self-determination in addiction. After some methodological reflections, I introduce a phenomenological description of the experience of being self-determined. I argue that being self-determined implies effectivity of agency regarding three different behavioural domains. Such self-referential agency shall be called ‘self-effectivity’ in this article. In a second step, I will use this phenomenological description to understand the impairments of self-determination in addiction. While addiction does not necessarily imply a basic lack of control over one’s life, this can well be the case during certain periods of time or in special situations. Addiction is herein described as an embodied custom—highly effective with respect to changing one’s lived experience—which is learned and developed while becoming addicted. Such a repeatedly performed custom, called a ‘psychotropic technique’, implies deep changes in one’s personal identity and alters an agent’s ‘self-effectivity’. In the closing section, I discuss the possible implications of a phenomenological approach to personal responsibility.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  1. Beauchamp, Tom L., and James F. Childress. 1989. Principles of biomedical ethics, 3rd ed. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Frankfurt, Harry G. 1999. Autonomy, volition, and love. In Necessity, volition, and love, 129–141. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  3. Schwartz, Michael A., and Osborne P. Wiggins. 2004. Phenomenological and hermeneutic models: Understanding and interpretation in psychiatry. In The philosophy of psychiatry, ed. Jennifer Radden, 351–363. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Sepp, Hans-Rainer. 2004. Epoché. In Wörterbuch der phänomenologie, ed. Helmut Vetter, 145–151. Hamburg: Felix Meiner.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Rinofner-Kreidl, Sonja. 2004. Representationalism and beyond. Journal of Consciousness Studies 11: 88–108.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Drummond, John J. 2007. Phenomenology: Neither auto- nor hetero- be. Phenomenology and Cognitive Science 6: 57–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  7. Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. 1999. Phénoménologie de la perception, 3rd ed. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Gallagher, Shaun. Forthcoming. Multiple aspects of agency. New Ideas in Psychology.

  9. Drummond, John J. 2008. Moral phenomenology and moral intentionality. Phenomenology and Cognitive Science 7: 35–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. Tengelyi, Laszlo. 2007. Narratives Handlungsverständnis. Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie S17: 61–73.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Kiekergaard, Søren. [1849] 1992. Die Krankheit zum Tode, 4th ed., trans. Emanuel Hirsch. Gütersloh: Gütersloher Verlagshaus.

  12. Yaffe, Gideon. 2001. Recent work on addiction and responsible agency. Philosophy & Public Affairs 30: 178–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  13. Talero, Maria L. 2008. The experiential workspace and the limits of empirical investigation. International Journal of Philosophical Studies 16: 453–472.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Gallagher, Shaun. 2007. The natural philosophy of agency. Philosophy Compass 2. doi:10.1111/j.1747-9991.2007.00067.x.

  15. Mishara, Aaron L. 2007. Is minimal self preserved in schizophrenia? A subcomponents view. Consciousness and Cognition 16: 715–721.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Holton, Richard. 2003. How is strength of will possible? In Weakness of will and practical irrationality, ed. Sarah Stroud and Christine Tappolet, 39–67. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  17. Schälike, Julius. 2009. Moralische verantwortung, freiheit und kausalität. Grazer Philosophische Studien 78: 69–99.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Watson, Gary. 2004. Disordered appetites: Addiction, compulsion and dependency. In Agency and answerability, ed. Gary Watson, 59–87. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Schlimme, Jann E. 2000. Sucht: Zur philosophischen anthropologie eines ‘misslingenden’ selbst. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Schlimme, Jann E. 2007. Zur psychiatrischen anthropologie der sucht. Der Nervenarzt 78: 97–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  21. Schlimme, Jann E. 2008. Versuch eines phänomenologischen verständnisses der sucht. Wiener Zeitschrift für Suchtforschung 31: 5–12.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Burroughs, William S. 1993. Naked lunch. London: Flamingo.

    Google Scholar 

  23. World Health Organization. 2007. International classification of disease, ICD 10. http://apps.who.int/classifications/apps/icd/icd10online/. Accesssed 23 September 2009.

  24. Heinz, Andreas, Thomas Siessmeier, Jana Wrase, Hans Georg Buchholz, Gerhard Gründer, Yoshitaka Kumakura, Paul Cumming, et al. 2005. Correlation of alcohol craving with striatal dopamine synthesis capacity and D2/3 receptor availability: A combined [18F]DOPA and [18F]DMFP PET study in detoxified alcoholic patients. American Journal of Psychiatry 162: 1515–1520.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  25. Waters, Roger. 1979. Comfortably numb [lyrics]. In The wall, ed. Pink Floyd. EMI.

  26. Kiefer, Falk, and Christoph von der Goltz. 2008. Lernen und gedächtnis in der pathigenese von suchterkrankungen. Der Nervenarzt 79: 1006–1016.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  27. Bateson, Gregory. 1976. Steps to an ecology of mind: Collected essays in anthropology, psychiatry, evolution, and epistemology. New York: Ballantine.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Dümpelmann, Leo. 1985. Versuch einer phänomenologie der handlung. Daseinsanalyse 2: 79–90.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Mertens, Karl. 1989. Kreativität ohne absicht? Bemerkungen zum verstehen kreativer leistungen. Phänomenologische Forschungen 14: 22–42.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Leon, Wurmser. 1978. The hidden dimension. New York: Jason Aronson.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Zingg, Christina, and Michael Soyka. 2009. Die bedeutung der selbstwirksamkeit für therapie und prognose der alkoholabhängigkeit. Nervenheilkunde 28: 514–517.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Borg, Margit, and Larry Davidson. 2008. The nature of recovery as lived in everyday experience. Journal of Mental Health 17 (2): 129–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. Elster, Jon. 1997. Strong feelings: Emotion, addiction, and human behavior: The Jean Nicod lectures. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Hume, David. 2000. A treatise of human nature. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I thank Michael A. Schwartz, Austin, Texas, and Friedrich M. Wurst, Salzburg, Austria, for discussing an earlier draft of my article. The work on the article was partially supported by a fellowship-grant from Hannover Medical School, Department of Psychiatry, Social Psychiatry, and Psychotherapy, Germany.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jann E. Schlimme.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Schlimme, J.E. Addiction and self-determination: A phenomenological approach. Theor Med Bioeth 31, 49–62 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-010-9134-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11017-010-9134-0

Keywords

Navigation